maanantai 19. marraskuuta 2012

The proper way of living


Physics that studies things that change in some manner, mathematics that studies invariable properties of these changing things and theology that studies invariable and perfect things are all according to Aristotle meant only to produce knowledge – after I learn how the universe is shaped, I can just enjoy my knowledge. Now, other type of learning changes not just the condition of our knowledge, but also makes us do something. Such practical studies are in Aristotle's opinion lower in status than the former, theoretical studies, because the practical studies are subservient to some external end – you don't study e.g. horseback riding just for the pleasure of study, but for the sake of learning to ride.

Now, all the practical studies form a sort of hierarchy – an art of riding horses might e.g. be subservient to the military science, because horses are ridden because of their usefulness in wars. Clearly, if there is some final end, which is desired for its own sake and towards which all human endeavors strive, there must also be the highest practical field of study, to which all other are subservient. Aristotle suggests that this highest practical study would obviously try to show how people should in general live. Of course, it would not go into details, but it would attempt to discern some general patterns peculiar to a decent living.

What then is the highest type of life for human beings? Aristotle first criticizes some views of contemporary thinkers. Many people would undoubtedly say that human beings life perfectly when they can satisfy all their lusts and desires. Aristotle rejects this possibility lightly: it is fit more for pigs than for human beings. Money is even worse contender for the proper satisfaction of life, because it is required only for the sake of obtaining something else, e.g. a decent living. Honour and reputation fair somewhat better, but these are too reliant on other persons, while a humanly perfect life should be as independent as possible of external influences. Finally, even having capacities is not enough for a fulfilling life – what if one never had to use them?

Another possibility Aristotle considers is the Platonistic idea that there is some perfectly good thing that somehow also makes other things good. Aristotle's dismissal is short. He merely points out that goodness has various meanings, but that such hypothetical source of goodness beyond what we can see and hear has really no relevancy to our life in concrete and diverse surroundings, but that the latter is what we as human beings want to obtain.

Aristotle's own theory starts from the idea that all animal species have some peculiar type of perfection that only they can fulfill. Thus, all plants nourish themselves and most of the animals use senses, and therefore these capacities cannot be the highest state of human being. Then again, the higher, more rational aspect of the human mind should on this account be an essential part of perfect human living. In general this perfection would consist of use and not just enjoyment of various human capacities: true purpose of humans lies in action.

Aristotle also suggests that the life of activity is not just what we should do, but also feels good, that is, if one is a person who lives well – pleasure is something that accompanies activity. True, some pleasures are corruptive, if they go to extremes, but still, pleasure in general wins its opposite or pain. Even bodily pleasures are good, when enjoyed in moderation, and a pleasure of a good life cannot be enjoyed too much. A good person is used to feeling pleasant sensations and emotions only for something perfect – otherwise, she would merely pretend to live a good life. Thus, she will also find her perfect activity a fulfilling and pleasurable experience.

Famous Greek thinkers had suggested that a person's life can never be perfect and a person can never be truly happy before her death – who knows what calamities would befall on a seemingly content person. And even when the person in question has lived her life perfectly her descendants might still do something horrible and stain the name of the family. Aristotle's answer is that a perfect life is almost completely unreliant on such matters of luck, because even in bad situations the person would use what is given to her in the best possible manner. Of course, the more livelihood a person has, the more opportunities for good action she has, but true virtue is shown by how a person uses what he has been given. Furthermore, the woes of the descendants cannot be criterion by which to decide the happiness of one's own life. On the other hand, mere lucky coincidences cannot on the long run serve the needs of a good life.

Activity is then the highest point of human experience. Aristotle continues by discussing various types of such a good life. The nutritive functions of our body are automatic, thus, not under our control and therefore not a concern of the search for highest human good. Then again, the functions peculiar to animals are in our control and are at least potentially in combat with the highest function of human being – reasoning. Thus, a good life consists partly in making one's sensuous impulses obey one's reason. Furthermore, a good use of reasoning forms the other part of good life.

Considering the first element of good life or the subservience of senses to reason, Aristotle notes that it is a matter of habituation to make one's impulses perfectly obey reason. One must e.g. venture into situations requiring courage in order to make oneself more courageous. Then again, merely doing courageous acts does not make one courageous, but one must understand that the action one is doing requires some courage.

In addition, one must voluntarily decide to act in a courageous manner to be truly courageous. That is, firstly, one must not be compelled to do the courageous thing by some external circumstances or by other persons – then again, one might be compelled to do it by one's desires and wants. Secondly, one must understand the nature of the courageous thing one is beginning to do – indeed, if a person regretted what he did after learning the true nature of his actions, he would clearly have acted against her true volition.

In fact, the courageous act must not be just voluntary, but one should have also chosen it. By choice Aristotle does not mean a mere wish that might or might not become real, but an action preceded by a process of deliberation. In such a deliberation person considers things that are under her own power and selects one possible course of action that she will take for a certain purpose. It is such deliberate choices that a person makes that are under moral scrutiny, not the actions that might be forced by external events, such as a threat of death.

Furthermore, one cannot recognize e.g. a courageous or otherwise virtuous person by her state of mind – such a state of mind, like anger or excitement, is itself neutral. On the other hand, a mere capacity for having certain state of mind is also not a good criterion, because such capacities are shared by all human beings. The true criterion is that the states of mind and actions of a person should be based on her stable character – a courageous person is disposed to act in a certain manner.

Just like with the general pattern of good life, we cannot exactly say when a student of virtue has found complete perfection in some area of life nor whether a particular action was completely what was required to do. What one can say, Aristotle continues, is to point out that one can fail in activity either by doing something too much or doing the same thing too few times. Thus, good habits can be seen as a sort of mean between two bad extremes. A person is then to be commended, if it is in her character to choose to do the proper action in a proper time.

Although a student of good life should try too veer away from both ”too much” and ”too little”, often it is natural for human beings to approach one direction. It is such natural aberrations that should especially be avoided, Aristotle says. For instance, it is far more natural to have too little courage than too much courage, thus, one should be more careful about being a coward than about being overly confident.

Aristotelian list of good things to do in bodily matters is clearly based on the standards and values of Greek society. Thus, Aristotle considers that one ought to control one's fear in grave dangers and especially during battle – although it is of course not good to attack enemies without any fear like barbarians. Furthermore, Aristotle commends persons who can control their desire for bodily pleasures like eating, drinking and having sex – still, he also admits that people can and should accept all natural forms of pleasure, because that is part of what being human means.

Courage in battle and resistance of pleasures are virtues of a warrior society, but Aristotle also considers more civilized activities. One should not hold on to every penny, but spend one's money on proper occasions and for noble purposes, although losing all for frivolities is foolish. One should strive for honour, but only by doing honorable things. One should not get angry on small things, but one should still not accept all insults without a say. One should not seek quarrels with other people, but one should still not be afraid of saying the truth, even if it hurts. One should not exaggerate one's merits nor should one understate them. One should know how to laugh and make others laugh, but still avoid cheap laughs. This rather long list of social virtues does not include modesty, because the habit of being ashamed suits only minors, while on Aristotle's opinion adults should have learned to refrain from shameful activities.

The second aspect necessary for good life is the use of one's intellect. The lowest form of this is when a person has the capacity to produce something, such as an artist who can make statues – this is the lowest form, because it requires meddling with things that have a tendency to change in various manners.

The highest form we met in the previous text: it is the Aristotelian wisdom, that is, a combination of an intuitive grasping of general unchanging principles governing everything and of a deductive system based on these principles. It is also, Aristotle says, highest form of good life, which also the Aristotelian divinity enjoys. Contemplation of eternal truths requires very little from a person, and therefore philosophers need not even the company of others when they use their wisdom. In comparison, less eminent virtues require a society in which they could be applied.

Between the capacity of production and wisdom lies the capacity peculiar for practical science, namely, the combination of an intuitive grasp of what is good and proper and of a capacity to apply this grasp in variable circumstances for determining suitable course of action. Aristotle notes that without this practical intelligence one cannot live a truly good life. One might still have an instinctual feeling of proper actions, which would be like a gift from God and thus not a mere coincidental piece of good luck – it is based on the nature and character of the person and not on accidental circumstances. Still, a mere instinct is not enough for life of rational human beings.

By defining what is a good way of life, Aristotle has also determined what sort of life is to be avoided. Now, there are two different manners of straying from the proper happiness of human beings. Firstly, one might be ignorant of true happiness, and for instance, think that excessive life of luxury will make one perfectly happy. Secondly, one might have a correct understanding of good life, but due to violent emotions or other conditions affecting one's mind fail to apply this knowledge – for example, a person addicted to alcohol might be in a state of mind where she can think of nothing else, but the immediate pleasure of drinking, although she would at other times well know the bad effects of over-drinking  Generally, it is especially the pleasures of the body that disturb such a weak character. Still, the weak character at least knows what she should really do and is thus more able to correct her way of life, while a truly bad character cannot even accept that she is doing something detrimental.

Corresponding to the two bad characters, there are two possible manners of living well. Firstly, one may be just so well habituated to the proper way of life that one will not even feel any temptation to go astray. Secondly, one might have all sorts of temptations, but one might still resist them, because one knows that these temptations will be bad – just like a person who desires to eat candies, but refrains from doing it, because it is bad for health.

The bad and the weak person are both governed by natural impulses, which have just become too excessive. Beyond these characters are persons who are governed by impulses for such unnatural actions as cannibalism – such persons cannot really be even condemned, Aristotle says, because they are completely without reason, although their actions are horrifying and inhuman. Aristotle also mentions that there is a corresponding level of goodness, where person's worth exceeds everything that is humanly possible.

Making people live a good life is for Aristotle an essentially social endeavour. Only a minority will follow the proper way of living because of ethical theories, while rest will need some help in breaking out of their bad habits. In large scale, such moral education should be provided by the community, although in practice this task is often left for the parents. Even they should have some knowledge of social relations, although Aristotle despairs of finding proper teachers for this topic: practical politicians have not theoretical capacities for explaining their practices, while sophists who present themselves as teachers of this topic have actually no idea of it.

Social life, on the other hand, is possible only because human beings sometimes want to do good things to one another. Sometimes they just feel sympathy for another person, but at other times they also actively try to improve the other's condition. Indeed, such mutually agreeable social relations Aristotle deems to be an essential part of a good life – others might help you through bad times, and you might gain honour by helping others. Thus, one has to see what things bind humans together in this manner.

One obvious answer is that people often have mutual interests and must thus act like business partners – this happens especially with more mature persons, who think carefully of what is useful to them. Such partnerships based on mutual profit often lead to arguments whether one has gained what one should have – and they very easily break down when their usefulness has ended.

Another reason for partnerships is that the persons involved find their intercourse somehow pleasant – perhaps they like the witty conversation or perhaps they have erotic feelings toward one another. Such partnerships occur most often among young people, who are more easily driven by their feelings. Such partnership or friendship is more lasting than one based on mere mutual profit, but can break down, if the interests and the feelings of the former friends change.

The most perfect form of partnership lies between two persons living a good life. Because they both can recognise how perfect a life the other lives, they must respect and like one another – thus, they will have a desire to interact with one another and to help the other if he happens to be in need. Such a friendship is based on the stable characters of the two persons and last therefore longest, although even they might break, if the moral character of one person should abruptly change for the worse or better. Yet, they are also the rarest sort of partnership, because the multitude of humanity does not understand what it means to live a good life.

The three types of partnerships are all based on the mutual similarity of the persons involved – they have mutual interests, share pleasures or are both good persons. Yet, also persons of unequal status do frequent one another's company. A person may be more useful to another than the other to him, he may give more pleasure to his friend or he may help the other to become a better person. In all such cases the person giving more should get in return more honour from his actions.

On the other hand, affection for oneself could be seen as a sort of limiting case of partnership. Such self-approval comes actually in two forms, Aristotle says. One might approve one's sensuous desires, and such self-approval should be despised. Then again, a person living a good life should surely also like oneself in the perfect sense of the partnership – after all, who would be more closer to one than oneself.

An important element of good social life is that all goods should be distributed according to the merits of the persons – the more a person gives to the community, the more she should also get from community. Here one could get more than one deserves and thus have an unfair advantage, or one could get less than one deserves and suffer injustice. The mean state is then where a person gets her just desserts. Just person is then one aiming always for that mean state.

The just distribution of goods is based on the worth of the persons involved, but justice in another sense is not related to this personal worth. That is, sometimes a person has in full awareness or accidentally got something that belongs to another person or in other way hurt that other person – for instance, she might have robbed and beaten someone. It is then a task of some mediator or judge to mitigate the wrong experienced by the other – and the judge should make her decision based on the act and not the character of the persons involved. A just judge is then one that can give correctly balanced retributions.

Both forms of justice presuppose some standard by which the goods and the bads can be measured. In general, we must be able to say e.g. how much one shoe is in comparison with one horse. Thus, societies have found it convenient to assign some items a task of serving as a measure of exchange – shoe pays for 5 coins, horse pays for 50 coins, thus, you could get a horse with ten shoes. It is then at least somewhat conventional what is just and what is not – in some cultures horses might be valued less and a just price of them would be less. Still, Aristotle thinks that there are some inherently just or unjust actions, although he does not clearly explain what they would be.

Furthermore, justice in general requires that the persons involved should be free of one another, Aristotle continues. Thus, if a person is property of another, the owner cannot fault the owned. Still, one can speak analogically also of just conduct towards slaves, children and wives, although it is not justice in the proper sense.

Justice occurs also only between two persons, although Plato had figuratively spoken of a balance between various characteristics of mind as justice. Aristotle's point is that justice/injustice requires at least two persons, one of whom tries to correct some harms she has suffered. If the two persons would actually be one and the same person, some of the gains of the person would actually be also her losses. This is actually an instance of a wider area of expertise: immoral actions cannot happen towards oneself. A suicide appears to be a counter example, but actually one must note that in suicide it is the community that has something to say about the death itself.

A special field of interpersonal relations is the household, which mostly consists of partnerships between unequals. The economy of Greek city states was based on slavery, and Aristotle was thus bound to accept that people had slaves, who had to obey their masters in all things. He justified the keeping of slaves by suggesting that some persons are naturally meant to be ruled, because they lack the proper resources of managing themselves and their own affairs. Natural masters, on the other hand, have a knack for seeing where the work of the slaves could be used best. Not surprisingly, Aristotle felt that non-Greeks on the whole had a more slavish nature than Greeks. Aristotle also admitted that often persons who had a natural right to be free were in fact enslaved – this happened especially in war, where all defeated were enslaved, although they would have the constitution of a ruler.

Just like masters were supposedly fit to rule natural slaves, Aristotle thought that adults have an essentially higher status than their children. Children have an untrained and raw constitution and therefore adults have the duty to raise them to be independent adults. Aristotle thought also that husband is naturally a better and more able person than his wife, from whom the husband should distinguish himself through his natural superiority. The closest to a true friendship of equals comes the relation of two brothers – and even here one brother is older and thus more respected.

Maintaining a household is not restricted to just governing the interpersonal relations in it, but one must also care for the material needs of the household by acquiring sufficient goods. Aristotle felt that the most natural way to acquire useful goods was to procure them with one's own efforts, e.g. through agriculture. If all needs could not be satisfied by oneself, one could also trade one's own products with those of others. These forms of acquiring goodness have natural limits determined by human needs, but there are also unnatural forms, whereby one e.g. uses money to gain more money – for instance, by giving loans with a interest. As the quest for more money can never be fulfilled, Aristotle commends ignoring it.

The existence of many different interpersonal relations causes the potential problem of preference: which relations should matter most when one cannot fully serve all of them, e.g. when the needs of one friend go against the needs of another? Aristotle notes that no hard and fast rules could be given for all cases, although some relations are more important than others, for instances, close relatives are usually to be respected more than other people.

The final step in the attachment of persons to one another is the creation of a community of several persons, where such a community could feel a similar concord as two friends or relatives. Aristotle felt that the drive towards forming communities is inherent in human nature. As community then is a natural whole, it will be in a sense more important than the individuals forming it – community is the end of the individuals and not the other way around. Even so, in a common type of community a completely perfect life cannot be lived, Aristotle continues: usually people have to take turns when to rule and when to be ruled in a community, while a perfect life would consist only of ruling.

An important question Aristotle considers is whom should we consider as members of any community. He rejected the idea that a community would consist of all people living in a certain area – then even slaves and foreign visitors should be considered part of the community. Indeed, a community is not just a collection of people, but a common undertaking of people for a good and noble life.

A true criterion of citizenship, according to Aristotle, is that a member or citizen of the community should take some part in the official proceedings of the community – thus, even children fail to be true citizens, before they grow up. A peculiar consequence of Aristotle's definition is that a community is automatically changed whenever the power relations between people change – still, Aristotle notes, the new community might have a duty to take care of some of the old community's debts.

Aristotle thought that a community should be large enough to be independent of other communities, but small enough to be governed in a reasonable manner. It should be close to sea to facilitate trade, although care should be taken that the foreigners wouldn't bring with them any bad influences. Climatewise Greece is an ideal place for communities, because it is warm enough to make intellectual life possible, but not so warm as to encourage luxurious life.

Now, the management of the community could be managed in several manners. A question of the best possible constitution for a community was a topic much discussed at the time, and Aristotle had lot to say on the various suggestions. Many people thought that e.g. the constitution of Sparta was the most optimal in existence. Aristotle did admit that there is much to commend in the Spartan manner of living, but still saw too many failings to be perfectly happy with it. The main problem was that Spartans had shaped their community for the sake of warfare, but had then ignored the actual management of the community's day-to-day affairs. The result was that the community didn't spare efforts for making its soldiers brave and skilled in martial arts, but did not take care that its rulers wouldn't take personal advantage of the spoils of war.

Plato's theorizing of an ideal community Aristotle found even more unsatisfactory. A particular piece of criticism concerned Plato's suggestion that the rulers of an ideal community should form a one big family, in which all wives and children would be shared. Aristotle notes that a community should not form as close a unity as a family – then it would not be a community, but a family. Furthermore, he was also convinced that Plato's scheme would not really make the bonds of the rulers as close as the bonds of family members – if affection was to be shared in a big group, it would be bound to be diluted, Aristotle thought.

Aristotle was thus not satisfied with mere theoretical categorizing of possible types of community, but he made careful research on what forms of government the different Greek cities had and how they had developed over time. Only on the basis of these investigations did he then construct a schematic classification of all possible governments.

Besides describing different communities, Aristotle also tried to discover how these communities collapsed and were replaced by other types and how such a collapse might be prevented. Plato had also theorised about the collapse of societies, but Aristotle felt Plato's ideas were lacking: Plato saw only a one line of progression from a constitution to another, while Aristotle admitted that there were several possible ways a community could change. Moreover, he was certain that communities sometimes changed only partially and might even keep the type of constitution, if the change in question was minor.

The primary principle Aristotle followed is that there is not a single recipe that all communities should follow, but that there are many possible options of governing a community: although one type of community would be best, it might not work for all communities. For instance, a rule of the best and the brightest can be justified by professionals knowing things better than laymen, but then again power of common people can also be justified by the argument that many eyes see things better than just one or few eyes. Furthermore, a rigid law is usually more stable than reliance on an unpredictable individual – still, if a person of a remarkable mental stature surpassing all laws were found, we would have to either banish him or relinquish all laws and make him the rightful king.

Thus, according to Aristotle's classification, the community could have a single leader caring for the well-being of his subjects – such a community would resemble the rule of a father towards his children. The paradigmatic case of such a monarchical community is a perfect absolute ruler knowing best what is good for everyone – an ideal community under an ideal governor with full authority. Still, there are monarchies, where the role of the king is more restricted and regulated through laws. In some cases king is just a fancy name for a master of ceremonies.

The main lack in the kingly rule is that it is too much based on the goodness of the ruler. If the ruler was somehow corrupted or if his follower had not the same qualities, the state of the community would quickly deteriorate  Aristotle therefore suggested that the rule of the king should be divided among many officials.

A single individual might err from a correct path, but several individuals could then correct the mistakes of one. Thus, one possibility for managing the community is that the governing should be left to a number of able men. These rulers would have a nature superior to their subjects, just like husbands are, according to Aristotle, wiser than their wives. If these able men were just like the divine ruler in the absolute monarchy, we would have another variation of the ideal community. Because of their worth, the rulers should be free of menial work. The number of the rulers would be kept limited through abortions and slaying of handicapped babies – a brutal practice common in Greek societies.

An important aspect of an ideal community was to be an education of future rulers – a task so important that it shouldn't be left to private citizens. The aim of the education shouldn't be warfare, but peaceful community life. Thus, the rulers should not just be trained in sports, but also in music – not so much to play, but to listen music. The education should begin by training the body and only then personality. In personality we should first educate the habits of the future rulers, and last the most important aspect of human life or intellect. After education is over, the citizens would at first spend a couple of years serving in military. In full maturity, they would become governors, and in old age, they would tend of religious cults.

In a somewhat less ideal type of constitution, the governors would be elected among the most able men of the rich and the noble. All constitutions based on a minority rule face the same problem – the group of truly able people is usually smaller than the group of people thinking they are able, which might thus lead to factions and civil disorder.

The final possibility is a constitution in which all citizens are at least in some measure able to control their lives – such a community would resemble the relation of brothers to one another. A majority of a community cannot be ideal rulers, hence, this sort of community could not be ideal. Still, it could be best that is possible in all circumstances and for all types of people. In this realistic option, no unfair advantage should be given either to the poor or to the rich. The poor would be encouraged to take part in politics by donating them money when they took part in public meetings, while the rich would be discouraged to shy away from politics by appointing fines if they avoided public meetings. Furthermore, Aristotle thinks that a strong middle class would be an essential element in keeping such a constitution in order – the middle class would have no desire to give too much power to either the poor or the rich. The problem is, of course, to guarantee that the balancing act works and doesn't tip to either extreme.

Indeed, these relatively good forms of government could also turn into caricatyric types, where the rulers would care only for themselves and not others. The search of a just share of votes might be replaced by the masses wanting to search gain for themselves. The poorer the masses are, the more extreme such a government would be. In milder forms of mass government, there are still laws that are followed, but in more extreme forms the whims of the rabble and demagogues exciting it rule everything. Such a rule of the rabble might quite easily descend into a complete tyranny, if the people gave their power to a single ruler. Instead, one should try to have more upper class people involved in the government, so that the rich would not be afraid that the poor will use the state to take away their money. Indeed, a good democracy should make all citizens more wealthy, so that no discontent factions would arise.

Then again, the aristocratic constitution based on the goodness of the governors could be changed into a community ruled by most powerful and wealthy – in a household such an event might occur, if e.g. a wife would be allowed to govern her man because of the money she owns. In some cases the upper classes might allow a movement upwards in the society, if the person involved would acquire the necessary financial means. In the worst case, one group of wealthy people would take complete control of the community and prevent anyone else having anything to do with government. The wealthy people might then turn into factions fighting one another. Then again, the rich might aggravate the poor to revolt their rule. If the rich wanted to make their rule stable, they should let even the less rich have some means of taking part in government. Furthermore, the governors should use their wealth to make the community as a whole a better place to live.

Finally, a king might become a tyrant, who rules everyone like master commands his slaves. Even such a tyrannical rule might be tempered by customs and laws, but in the most extreme case, one man would govern anything according to his own wishes and desires. Tyrannical communities are the least stable of governments – its weak points include the possibility of another person grapping hold of the tyrant's position and the possibility of the poor leading a revolution. The tyrant might improve his chances by using literally tyrannical methods and e.g confiscating the property of suspicious individuals. Another possibility would be to make tyranny into a more king-like constitution by showing good example to all citizens.

sunnuntai 29. huhtikuuta 2012

The moment of perfection


According to Aristotle, the progress from sense perception through memory and experience to true knowledge involves growing generalisation: while in perception we see only singular appearances, in experience we become acquainted with a number of objects of the same sort and in knowledge we can finally recognise that objects of certain sort necessarily have certain characteristics. The generalisation means loss of some concreteness – ”animal in general” is not coloured or at least does not have any peculiar colour. Still, it also allows us to deal with a set of various objects in a conveniently short manner.

Aristotle envisioned that the generalisation progress would have a limiting point, which he described as the first philosophy – not first in the order of learning, but first in the sense of importance. This first philosophy would be farthest from concrete experiences, but still deserves the name wisdom as the final aim of human endeavours. Note how Aristotle here moves away from the original meaning of wisdom as the capacity to know how humans should live – Aristotelian wisdom is far above such pragmatic concerns.

In this primary field of inquiry one should e.g. determine what facets of an object are required for its proper description. Aristotle noted that most of the earliest philosophers had exhaustively described how every-day objects are made out of materials like water and air. Only some had had the idea of describing basic forces that were supposed to activate the combination and recombination of materials. Platonists had had some inkling that describing the structures of the things would help in explaining them, although they had apparently thought of these structures as things independent of the every-day things, thus needlessly multiplying the number of entities. Finally, many of the previous thinkers and poets had emphasised how the world was good or in accord with some purposes. These four facets – materials out of which things are made of, forces changing the things, structures characterising the things and the purpose for the sake of which things exist – are then the only things required for a complete description of a thing and its processes.

Aristotle also noted that description of all the four facets must end at some point. If a statue is made of bronze, bronze is made of further elements and so on, this progression of constitution must end at some ultimate material, which is not made of anything. Similarly, everything embodies various structures – it is e.g. brazen, statue, likeness of a Greek philosopher etc. – but some structure of the thing is full in the sense that the thing cannot be modified or structured any further. Furthermore, changes of a thing must begin from some first change, and the changes must have some ultimate goal, which has not been striven for because of a further goal.

There would then have to be four different sorts of ultimate principles, from which all explanations and descriptions should begin. The problem is whether all of the four principles should be investigated by the same field of philosophy or whether they all should have their own disciplines. The problem boils down to the question what is the common topic uniting all the four major principles. Aristotle's answer is that as they are principles required when describing anything there is, the primary philosophy should study literally everything there is – trees, humans beings, lakes and everything else. Yet, the primary philosophy should not be interested of characteristics peculiar e.g. to trees, but only of characteristics common to all things there are.

What should the primary philosophy investigate then? Aristotle noted that the phrase ”being” might well have different meanings – we may say even that there are holes in my sock, although holes are things of very different sort from socks. Still, Aristotle thought that we could find some primary meaning of being, to which all other meanings of the word would be related. After all, there wouldn't be any holes without socks or other ”holed” objects – thus, there are clear levels of primacy among different beings, and presumably, a most primary level of beings.

A further problematic concerns the question what are the actual characteristics that are to be found in this primary level of things. Aristotle himself started from the fact that – at least in Greek – adding the phrase ”one” added nothing to the meaning of a word: ”one man” means precisely same as mere ”man”. Thus, any object studied by primary philosophy should also be in some sense ”one”: that is, a distinct unity. Aristotle also recognised that things could be ”one” or same in many different senses – some things are unified by belonging to same class, others by having been made of same stuff, that is, by being the exactly same thing. Furthermore, any discipline studying a characteristic like unity should also discuss the lack of this characteristic, which in this case should apparently be plurality, which also has many senses like oneness. Aristotle then suggested that all characteristics definable through the concepts of unity and plurality should be part of the primary philosophy. For instance, a thing is something else than a given thing, if they are made of different stuff, and they differ, if they don't have same qualities.

Furthermore, Aristotle stated that the primary philosophy should also study the primary truths from which all other truths are to be derived, because these truths should be valid for all beings. Aristotle does not mean that the primary philosophy should literally prove these truths, because they in fact should be presupposed by all demonstrations. Yet, the primary philosophy could still in some measure at least defend these truths. Thus, one could defend the most primary truth of them all: that nothing can both be and not be something at the same time and in the same respect. Aristotle is not so much concerned of people who deny this principle in some cases: one might very well say that e.g. an object looks white and does not look white, that is, depending on the perspective from which the object is looked at. Even in these cases people would mostly admit that there is some primary level of discussion in which the principle does hold – for instance, the statement saying that an object looks differently coloured from different perspectives might be true in all contexts, while its opposite would be false in all contexts.

It is the person denying the validity of the principle in all cases Aristotle worries most. In effect, the denial would mean the denial of any absolute standpoint – all statements would be true in some sense and false in another. Aristotle himself pointed out that such a position would rule out all meaningful discussion. Indeed, it would make everything a complete chaos. Furthermore, it would make all decisions pointless: because I would always both exist and not exist, it would be just as same if I just would go and throw myself off a cliff.

The denial of contradictions appears then to be required at least in some primary level, and similarly one should accept the statement that all things either have a characteristic or not, Aristotle continued. True, one could suggest that the process of changing from one characteristic to another would constitute a third possibility. Yet, one would still have at least some definite possible characteristics of which a thing should have at least one – definitely being something, definitely not being something and being in a process of changing from one state to another. The only other possibility would be to accept an indefinitely numerous set of mediating states – a process from a state of being something to a state of changing this state, a process from the original state of being something to the the previous process etc. Thus, the statement of definite options should be also accepted at least in some level.

The primary truths apply then at least to the primary level of beings, but the question is, what this primary level consists of. The problem is deepened by the ambiguity in the use of the word ”being”. Firstly, ”being” is used in phrases like ”this is so and so”, where we affirm that some statement is true, that is, that certain thing can be characterised in a particular manner. Yet, true statements are clearly not as essential as the things that we state something about – statements are dependent on human beings, while things in general might not be.

Secondly, in a related sense, we might say simply ”it's this”, when we just apprehend some thing. This is also a true statement, but true in the sense of coming in contact with something: an opposite state would not be an assertion of false statement, but a state of not coming in contact with the thing. Still, even here the statetement is not as essential as the thing contacted. Thus, truth in general does not constitute the primary level of being.

Furthermore, we could speak of a thing being something accidentally, just like a quack might manage to cure his patient, if he gets lucky. Such accidences cannot be systematically studied, just because they are mere accidences – we cannot say why it was a quack who did the curing, because his quackness had nothing to do with the curing, and indeed, quacks usually don't cure people. The primary level is then not to be identified with any mere accidental features that might change from one situation to another.

Now, in all changes there is something that remains same throughout the whole process: for instance, when a piece of bronze is made into a statue, the statue is still a thing made of bronze, although its original shape has changed. We might thus suppose that what remains constant in all possible changes constitutes the primary level of being. Then again, this constant element would not be in itself cut into individual pieces, because this would require a further structurisation of this ”prime matter”. Yet, it appears evident that the primary entities are individual things of some sort and thus not a mere shapeless unity of matter.

It then might appear that structured pieces of this stable element underlying all changes would fit the role of primary beings. This is what we actually suppose normally, because cats, planets and rocks are just such structured pieces of matter. One could say that even abstract geometrical entities - such as lines, triangles and cubes – are structured pieces of a stable space and so also fit this supposed definition of primary level. In fact, all things that can be defined (e.g. human being) can be analysed as being further structurations (rational) of a stable element capable of being structured in several manners (animal). Only indefinable primary concepts cannot be described in this manner.

The problem is that these structured pieces are obviously dependent on the stable element and on the structure. Indeed, the most familiar of these structured pieces are suspectible to destruction, just as they have been generated, e.g. a cat is born and dies. The case of generation and destruction actually suggests that the structures are more stable than the structured things. In case of living beings, a living being that begins the process of generating another living being uses some material by giving it a similar structure to what it itself has, just like a cat is conceived by other cats. In artificial production, on the other hand, the producer at least thinks of the structure she wants to embody and uses the materials for producing this embodiment. Furthermore, there is the third possibility that something accidental begins a process of generation, but even then the structured element must have had a capacity for being structured in this manner. While ordinary things come and go, their structures remain, and it even seems meaningless to ask how e.g. a structure of life could be destroyed.

Aristotle finds other reasons for upholding the primacy of the structures. People can express wonder for various things: say, ”cow – sick?”, ”thunder – tonight?” or ”Madonna – in Moscow?”. These expressions of wonder, which could be turned into why-questions, have the same shape: they express wonder of a feature that some thing has. The wonder might be answered by determining the factor causing the feature – what made the cow sick or generated thunder tonight – or by determining the purpose for the feature – for what reason Madonna chose to travel to Moscow.

Aristotle then noted that one could also express wonder of the thing itself and not just its feature. In one sense such wonder is irrational: it is self-evident that e.g. horses are what they are. Yet, the wonder in this case is explicable – we are wondering e.g. what makes these bones, blood and other tissues into a unitary being that we can call a horse. Aristotle notes that it is simply that these constituents take on a certain structure, that is, the structure of a horse.

It appears then that it is the structure that is the most primary constituent: in other words, the important question is not what something is made of, but what it is made into, i.e. what its essential nature is. Of course, there are also secondary structures. Hence, we could speak of the structure of whiteness and we might even find a suitable definition for something being white. Yet, just like such accidental features are not beings in the primary sense, also only the things of primary level have a structure in a much stronger manner.

Furthermore, individual things cannot really be captured merely by their structure, because in addition to their structure, the things have also the material from which they have been made. Of course, we could add to the definition of a thing the material, but this would still not individuate the thing enough – even if we would have two structurally identical statues made of bronze, they both would still be made of a different pieze of bronze and would still be different things.

Structures thus appear to be something that could be shared by a number of things, but this has its own problems, because the primary things are usually thought as individuals. One possibility might be to assume that the structures would be indeed independent individuals, which would somehow make material objects assume shapes resembling themselves, somewhat like in Plato's theory of ideas. Yet, Aristotle at once points out the dilemma that such an assumption just begs the question: what then structurises these supposed ideal structures?

Aristotle's final answer is that the primary level of beings depends on the context. The stable element common to various things has the capacity to become any of these things, just like bronze can take various shapes. When the capacities are activated, a certain concrete thing is generated, and when the activating element is removed, the concrete thing is destroyed – thus, we might say that a shapeless blop of bronze is less primary or less active than a statue made of it. Finally, what makes the stable element into a concrete thing and thus activates its capacities is the structure. One might still ask what then combines the stable element and the structure. Aristotle's answer is that they just are defined as being necessary complements to one another: the stable element has the capacity to be structurised in some manner, if suitable external influences affect it, while the structure is just the activation of this potential capacity.

Because the components of the primary level are explained through concepts of potential capacity and its activation, Aristotle accordingly proceeds to analyse these terms. He notes that potentiality in Greek means primarily something that can be changed by some external element, just like a piece of bronze can be sculpted into a statue. More generally even things that cause changes may be said to have potential capacities, just like fire has the capacity of burning a forest.

In many cases, capacities belong to inanimate things or to animals incapable of choosing their own actions. Such capacities can only be passively activated by suitable circumstances, just like fire grows when oxygen is present and a starving animal starts to salivate when it senses food. Then again, a free agent with a capacity – say, a doctor – can choose not to use her activities and might even use it for contrary purposes, just like the doctor might use her medical knowledge for killing a person.

When does then a thing have a capacity for something? Megarian school had suggested that a thing had potential capacities only when it truly used them. Aristotle noted that this idea would lead to obvious absurdities: whenever we were not doing sums, we would lose our capacity for arithmetic. Aristotle himself noted that some capacities were inherent in natural properties of some things, just like eyes have the capacity for seeing. Then again, acquired capacities were usually received in whole when one for the first time used them, just like a practicing architect could be said to have the capacity for building only when she has built a house.

In rare cases Aristotle accepts capacities that do not have a corresponding actual result, for instance, a capacity for infinite divisibility of matter can never be wholly activated, because there is no final point at which the divisibility would end. Most of the time, an activation of capacity results in something that differs from the capacity, but also from the process of activation: this process is limited by the actual result. The result might be a thing generated through the activation of the capacity, such as a house made by an architect. In more important cases, the result of the activation is itself an activity, just like the activation of generative processes of life causes the beginning of a new process of life of a living individual. Such an activity would have no external end it would try to acheive, unlike the process of activation.

Aristotle notes that we cannot really speak of the capacity without mentioning the result of its activation – capacity of sight is just a capacity for seeing something. Then again, the result can be mentioned without mentioning the capacity. In general, the result is more essential than the capacity: the capacity is desired for the sake of acheiving the result, and not the other way around. True, capacities do appear to be prior in time, because one must have the capacity, before one can activate it. Yet, the result must often exist before the capacity in another individiual thing – thus, although a fetus might have the capacity to become a horse, the fetus itself is preceded by other horses which have conceived the fetus.

The primary level of being has thus been discovered, but it is not yet clear what classes this primary level is divided into. We know already from the Aristotelian physics that there are things that have a tendency to change in various ways, when left to their own devices. Some of them, the earthly things, changed in an irregular manner, while the celestial objects appeared to move eternally in a constant manner. An interesting problem lies in the question whether only those things studied by the physics exist: if this would be so, the primary philosophy would be only the most general stage of physics.

Aristotle does appear to accept beyond physical things also mathematical objects, which cannot be physical, because the do not change their nature – a triangle has always three sides, as long as it is a triangle. Yet, these objects cannot really be independent objects, because then the connection of mathematics with actual triangles would become incomprehensible. Instead, objects of mathematics are only physical things, when we disregard their material substrate and consider only their geometric form and quantity – there is no abstract heaven of triangles, but only actual triangles, which can e.g. change their shape. Other possible candidates for non-physical or invariable objects would be Platonic ideas. Yet, accepting such objects as independent of the natural things causes several problems, for instance, it unpurposefully adds a layer of objects beyond what we can see and hear.

Still, the eternal motion of stars does require something beyond mere physical things that will keep the heavenly spheres moving – and the stars must move eternally, or otherwise we must presuppose a sudden point of time in which everything in the world started inexplicably. Even a mere potential capacity for moving the stars would not be sufficient, because such a capacity might accidentally stop working. Instead, this moving principle should be constantly active in the same manner.

Because it cannot then change its state, it must be in the most perfect state possible for it and indeed for anything. Yet, it would still be constantly active, but its action would have no other goal beyond its own self-satisfaction – the perfect thing would live in an enduring orgastic moment. Aristotle suggested that the nearest we can ever come to feel the same as the perfect thing is when we without any external purpose think some fairly abstract philosophical issues and take pleasure in our capacities for handling such difficulties.

Aristotle deplored the idea that this epitome of perfection would go on turning the crank that moved the universe: this would make it seem like this perfect thing or God would want something by causing the movement happen. Instead, the God does not will to move the universe, but merely inspires the universe to move with its very existence – it is so perfect that the sphere of the stars tries to imitate it by its own constant movement, and from the heavens the movement the passes to Earth.

Aristotle also appeared to waver in the question, whether there are only one or more of these perfections. On the one hand, all the planets appeared to need their own governing principles that kept their movement going on. On the other hand, there are various difficulties in accepting more than one perfect being. The sensible things can be differentiated at least through their different matter: even two pieces with the same structure can be made of different materials or at least different pieces of the same stuff. Now, material of structures was to be analysed in terms of potential capacities: bronze is just something that can be used for brazwn objects. But the perfect being would have no potentialities and thus it could not have any individuating matter. Hence, it appears that there could be only one perfect thing.

Whatever the case, the perfect being would be the apex of a hierarchy based on the notion of perfection, high above mere mortals. Indeed, this perfect being would be the source of all perfection and goodness in the world – the perfect thing inspires others. So, the primary philosophy lies in close connection with these theological speculations – all beings receive their meaning from the perfect being.

maanantai 20. helmikuuta 2012

Moving towards perfection


We saw last time the ideal of knowledge in Aristotle, but what is still lacking is the actual knowledge. Now, whereas in Plato there was one overreaching question – how to live a good life – governing whole of his philosophy, Aristotelian philosophy was governed by several questions. First of them might be: ”what is there and what is it like?” The aim of of this question was to find a vision of things and their essences: vision or theoria, which is why this part of philosophy was known as theoretical.

The experience appears to suggest as the first answer to the theoretical question that there are things that change in a number of ways. As we have seen, this viewpoint had been contested by Eleatics, who believed that there was only one existing thing and therefore nowhere that a change could lead to. Aristotle was quick to note that such a standpoint could not be properly handled in a science that assumes the existence of change. Still, he explained that Eleatic arguments could be understood as linguistic confusions. Thus, even if there would be only one existing entity, this entity could have a number of states, between which a change could happen. Furthermore, the Eleatics had at least described this supposed unitary entity with many terms: it was, for instance, either limited or unlimited. Such a description was then something different from the entity itself, and hence, in a sense even Eleatics had to accept multiplicity.

Because Eleatic arguments could then be ignored, we could accept the testimony of our senses and believe in the existence of change. Change, furthermore, seems to involve the existence of multiple states or things. A further question was then how many features one had to assume in order to account for change. Aristotle found Anaxagoras' theory of change insufficient. As we should remember, Anaxagoras had merely pointed out that e.g. a change of food to flesh could occur, because the constituents of flesh were among the constituents of food. Anaxagoras could then just say that constituents of everything were among constituents of everything else: as Aristotle pointed out, this explanation explained really nothing, because it didn't reveal what these constituents were.

Aristotle was then after a determinate number of features involved in change. His predecessors passed onto him two hints of these features. Firstly, many of earlier philosophers had noted that all change happened between two extreme states, like unity and multiplicity or hot and cold: indeed, all change moves from one state to another. Secondly, especially Platonists had assumed that the world of change was constituted by two things: a disordered chaos and an unchanging source of order regulating this chaos.

Now, Aristotle combined these two insights. The first extreme state of any change could be identified with some Platonic source or idea, or as Aristotle preferred to call it, form: a change either started or ended with a state of having some characteristic, such as the characteristic of being a doctor. The other extreme would then undoubtedly be a state of not having a characteristic. Platonic school had called this negative state matter, but Aristotle thought this was more of a confusion. Plato had not noticed a source of some characteristic could not affect a mere lack of itself (e.g. a mere lack of a doctor cannot become an existence of a doctor without anything to cause this generation of a doctor). Instead, change presupposed that something changed and this subject of change remained existent for the whole duration of this change: for instance, a person who is not doctor might become a doctor through proper education. This underlying thing that remained constant throughout any change could then be regarded as a third element in change, and indeed, this is what Aristotle preferred to call matter.

A certain type of change interested Aristotle partircularly, that is, changes that happened, when things were left to their own devices. Such changes could be called natural, and because Greek word for nature was physis, the study of these changes was called physics. Although the modern physics is a descendant of Aristotelian physics, there are certain clear differences. For instance, in Aristotle's physics it is the biological changes that are especially paradigmatic.

As we might remember from Aristotle's notion of sciences in general, any science should try to determine four aspects of the things it studies. Firstly, one ought to look for the conditions required for something: in case of changes one of these conditions was that what remained stable throughout the change or matter from which the result of the change was made. Secondly, one should try to find out what is the essence of what we are studying: in case of natural changes it is especially the essence of the result of the change we are interested in. Thirdly, one should try to ascertain what made the thing investigated: in this case, what initiated the change. Finally, one ought to find out what is the purpose of the investigated thing, and in this case, the purpose of the change. Now, in case of biological changes the aim of the change is often just to preserve the life of the individual or its genus: thus, the purpose and the essence of the change coincide. Furthermore, the initiating factor of the change is either the living being itself or an individual of the same kind. Hence, one could merely speak of two aspects in these cases – matter and essence or form of the biological change – and Aristotle assumes this is true of almost all natural changes.

Besides natural changes, the things of nature are often affected by chance occurrences. In such cases the occurrences themselves usually are natural, but they have unexpected consequences: for instance, it is natural that a stone falls down, but the falling stone may accidentally also hit a person's head and kill her. Aristotle noted that many earlier philosophers had believed all changes to be based on mere chance: for instance, Empedocles had suggested that in the past there had been generated accidentally all sorts of animals – bulls with human head, for instance – and that only some had been able to live and perpetuate their species. Aristotle noted that although nature did show such chance occurrences, clearly all the natural changes were somehow inevitable, unless some other circumstances prevented them from happening. Yet, such changes were not caused by some clockwork mechanism, because they clearly strived for some end, like perpetuation of species.

What then changes in general involve? According to Aristotle, all changes activated some capacities inherent in that which changed: when I start to build a bookshelf, the capacity of the planks and the nails to be reconfigured in some manner is actualised, and when a leaf starts to turn red, its capacity of being red is activated. Yet, in the state of change this activating process is not yet complete: a leaf turning to red is not yet completely red. Instead, the changing object has activated merely its capacity of being potentially something: a leaf turning to red is on its way to becoming red and is in a more essential sense potentially red than it was before. Changes thus differ from activities like seeing which has no other end except seeing itself: a change moves towards some perfection, which is distinct from the change and in which the change itself ends.

Many of the earliest philosophers had supposed that changes required some sort of limitless source from which new thing could proceed – otherwise, the changes would someday cease, when everything that could come to be would have come to be. Aristotle noted that we need not assume such limitless or infinite source of change, because changes could keep on happening between different possible states: e.g. a same object could constantly turn from red to green and from green to red. Aristotle was generally quite sceptical of any infinities. Certainly there were no infinite bodies, he insisted, because in an infinite universe we would have no meaningful way to differentiate between different directions and thus it would be senseless to say that e.g. heavy bodies move downwards. Then again, infinity was an acceptable concept, if it merely referred to some process being capable of indefinite continuation. Thus, time could be infinite in the sense that time could continue indefinitely, division of areas and lines could continue ”infinitely” or indefinitely long – although in a finite universe there could be only finite areas and lines – and no number of objects was the largest (although there was a smallest number).

Aristotle noted that changes could be classified in different manners. In some cases, what is said to change is not actually what changes, but it is only a part of that which changes or a whole, part of which is changing: thus, if a man is moving, his thoughts may be said to move with him, or when an eye is healing, we may say that the body with the eye is also healing. Yet, in all such cases there must be some primary thing that truly changes.

Now, in some cases, change involved a creation of a new entity or then a destruction of something: when I build a house, the house itself did not exist before the building. Aristotle noted that it was a controversial question whether any true creations or desrructions truly occurred, because in a sense, all changes must involve the continuation of existence: new existents (houses) are generated from previous existents (bricks) and not out of nothingness. Still, Aristotle thought, we can speak of generation and destruction when a substantial change happens, like when an elementary stuff is changed into another sort of elementary stuff. Thus, a generation of one substance involves always a destruction of another substance.

In most of the changes, nothing is created or destroyed, but some feature of an existing thing is altered. This feature might be a quality that is not essential to the thing in question – like when a leaf turns red. At other times even the shape of the thing might remain what it is, but the quantity of the thing might change into bigger or smaller – like when a balloon expands. In some cases no feature of the thing changes, but the thing merely moves from one place to another.

Aristotle was also sure that if we ignored creations and destructions, things could change in a primary sense only in these three manners: qualitatively, quantitatively or from one place to another. Things could still change incidentally in other manners: thus, when all childs of a person dies, the person also incidentally stopped being a parent, although no change had happened to her personally. Particularly, Aristotle thought that changes cannot be said to properly change or come to existence or to be destroyed: otherwise, all changes would involve an infinite number of other changes.

The possibility of moving from one place to another suggests the question what places in general are. Clearly a place is not a feature of the body in it: otherwise, another object could not take the place of another (like one leaf cannot take the colour of another leaf). Instead, the place of an object is, primarily, the innermost surface of things embracing the object in question: thus, the place of wine is the inner surface of the bottle where the wine is situated. Secondarily, the place of the object is then any place where any place of the object is situated: thus, because the bottle is in the fridge, the wine may be said to be in the fridge, and because the fridge is in the kitchen, the wine is also in the kitchen. The ultimate place in which everything then is situated is the outer fringe of the universe – remember that Aristotle argued for the finity of the universe, because otherwise we could not situate anything anywhere in a meaningful way.

Although Aristotle thus accepted the idea of an ultimate system of places or space, he was not convinced that space could exist without anything to fill it. Atomists had endorsed the idea of empty space, because they couldn't conceive how anything could move without there being something empty to which it could move. Aristotle noted that the movement could still happen, if the things would just change their places with one another. Furthermore, in empty space nothing could move, according to Aristotle: all motion required some push from other objects, but in an empty space nothing would push an object to move. On the other hand, in empty space all things would move with infinite speed: speed of a thing was, Aristotle suggested, proportional to the resistance of medium in which the movement happened, but in a void with no resistance, the speed would grow impossibly large. It is easy to laugh at such deductions, when we know better, but the Aristotelian notions of movement and space might seem more natural, if we knew nothing of inertia.

In addition to space, movement is also connected with time. Indeed, time appears to be essentially related to change. Even if we were in a dark cave and saw nothing happening, but something changed in our thoughts, we could be certain that time went forward. Time is then, Aristotle suggests, the act of counting out all changes and especially movement: the moment of ”now” moves through various changes and determines what happened before and after and at what rate. Although the counting might be something we humans do, time itself is in another sense not dependent of human beings, because the things counted or the temporal processes would occur even without human beings. Aristotle also suggests that a natural way to measure time would be to use some cyclical and recurring process, like the revolution of planets.

Aristotle was certain from experience that spatial magnitudes form a continuum: that is, e.g. volumes that are next to each other or that have nothing between them have limits that touch one another and that cannot be separated from one another. Aristotle concluded from this definition of spatial continuum that it could not be formed of indivisible points – if point would be continuous with another point, their limits would coincide and be inseparable, and because points have no other limits, but points themselves, the points would actually be identical with one another. Indeed, two points cannot be even immediately next to each other in space, because two different points will have some line between them. Aristotle noted also that if space was a continuum, motion through space must also be continuous (otherwise a moving object could instantly move from one area of space to another separate from the area it had occupied), if motion was continuous, so also the passage of time (because time measures all motions), and if passage of time was continuous, so finally all changes (because time measures also other changes).

Aristotle's idea of continuum was explicitly meant to show why Eleatic and especially Zeno's proofs against the existence of motion were invalid. Zeno had argued that an object couldn't move, because at any one moment it was in some place resting. Aristotle answered that time does not consist of moments, although it is limited by moments: when we divide a process, we find just smaller processes, but no indivisible unit of processuality. The so-called ”now” was then, according to Aristotle, no part of time, but a limit between past and future periods of time.

If Zeno's first argument targeted the idea of motion as consisting of indivisible moments, his other argument tried to combat the idea of continuous movement and time by noting that it involved a movement through an infinite number of points that would take infinitely time. Aristotle noted that although space, moved through by an object, did contain the possibility of being divided into smaller and smaller points with evermore limiting points, these limits did not really stop the motion for any time, unless the object stopped for a moment at such limit point: but the motion would take an infinite time only if the object stopped at every possible limiting point, because the smaller pieces of motion take up smaller periods of time.

We have already seen how Aristotle assumed the existence of changes. Furthermore, he was certain that changes had happened always and would always happen: indeed, because time was for Aristotle a measure of change, no time without change could exist. In addition, changes could not have begun from a generation of moving things, because all changes require something existent: even changes where new entities are formed, such as a construction of a chair, require some previous matter from which the new entity is made. Finally, time of change could not be preceded by a period of eternal rest of all entities: otherwise, there must have been some object hindering the possible changes, and the supposed first change would have to be preceded by the destruction of this hindering element.

Then again, Aristotle also was certain that not all things were changing at any current moment. Qualitative and quantitative changes would end at some time – becoming red when the changing thing had became red and growing at least when the growing thing reached the size of the finite universe. The only change that might continue forever would be motion, but experience appeared to confirm that not all things were moving: for instance, a stone might be restfully lying on the ground. Finally, some things apparently start changing, while others stop changing.

Aristotle also thought it reasonable to assume that all moving and changing things were moved or changed by something: either by some part of themselves or something separate from them. In case of forced changes this seems obvious, but unforced or natural changes seem a different case. Yet, even natural changes (like the fall of a heavy object) could be said to be caused by things that either changed the nature of the thing changing (e.g. the thing that solidified moisture in the clouds to snow that then would naturally fall down) or released the thing from any hindrances to its natural motion (like a person sawing table legs causes a table to fall down). Furthermore, even in the so-called self-moving entities, like animals, one could separate between the moving aspect and the moved aspect. Thus, all changes would be caused by things other than the things changing.

The next question would then be whether all moving things would be moved by some moving thing or whether there could be movements and changes instigated by something immovable: because Aristotle equated nature with the realm of moving and changing things, this immovable would have to be beyond nature. Aristotle approached the question by noting that a moving thing can be said to move another thing only if the original moving thing moves at the same time than the moved thing. Because the moving thing would require then another moving thing to move it, there would at the same limited time be an infinite number of moving things and thus an infinite amount of motion. As Aristotelian universe was limited, such an infinite motion during a limited time appeared an impossibility to him.

Although the consideration of such an unchanging cause of changes would indeed not belong in an investigation of changing things, one still must ponder what sort of changes this primary initiator would cause. Because this initiator does not itself change in any manner, it can initiate only a change that occurs constantly and goes on continuously. Clearly such change cannot be a generation of a new entity, destruction of an old entity, change from one quality to another or growth or diminution of an object, because such changes all have a final limit, beyond which they cannot continue. Neither can it be movement in a straight line, because in a finite universe, such a motion must eventually stop. The only remaining possibility then is that the primary initiator causes something to move around in a circle for eternity.

Most of the things Aristotle has discussed thus far are at the fringe of what nowadays is called physics, and indeed, might be classified as metaphysics.When Aristotle comes to more concrete matters, the more dated his discussions appear. Still, it is worth to look at the cosmology of Aristotle more carefully because of its long-lasting influence. Note that although later generations were to treat Aristotle's natural philosophy as a fully completed system, it was always more of a work in progress – thus, Aristotle knew that there were many open problems, answers to which were merely speculated by Aristotle and his followers.

We have seen that in Aristotelian universe of changing things, some things change sometimes, while others are in a continuous process of change, and more particularly, move in circles. Aristotle explains the difference between these two things by suggesting that the things moving in circles are made of different stuff than the other things, namely, from a stuff that naturally moves in circles. Because of the continuous nature of circular movement, this stuff seems more primary than other sorts of matter.

Aristotle feels also convinced that there is only one sort of matter moving naturally in circles: the circular movement defines this stuff. Still, there can be places in which this stuff is more concentrated than in others. Such spots appear to us as emitting light in comparison with the other heavenly regions. Aristotle also suggests in some passages that these spots are living and perhaps even conscious entities.

Aristotle also thinks that the world of the circularly moving stuff is divided into different layers: this is his attempt to explain the astronomical knowledge of his times. The outermost layer moves in a circle and the concentrated spots are carried by the layer: these spots are what we would call stars, which appear to move around the Earth in one day. This layer and its denizens are the most perfect moving things. Slightly lesser perfect are the spots moving in the inner laeyrs of the circularly moving stuff. The layers themselves move around the Earth, but the movement of the outer layers makes the spots also move within their own layers: this causes the apparently erratic movements of the planets. In the innermost layers the effect of the outer layers apparentyly twindles, because the layers moving the Sun and the Moon move again in a simpler manner. Aristotle also connects this structural difference of the layers with their corresponding levels of perfection: the stars in the outermost layer achieve the highest state of bliss through a simple movement, the planets require more effort to achieve this state and the Sun and the Moon cannot even achieve this level of perfection.

The circling movement of the heavenly stuff requires some fixed point around which it moves. This unmoving body should then be made of stuff that differs from the heavenly stuff. Indeed, the immobility of the central body or Earth is explained by the fact that the stuff which it is mostly made of – earth – moves naturally towards the centre of the universe: earth moves only when it is forcefully taken away from the center, and when it arrives at the centre, it stops moving.

The Earth differs then from stars and planets, because it allows the movement of bodies to stop. Indeed, the movements of earthly bodies seem to be of many different kinds. Aristotle now believed that this multiplicity of motions could be analysed through the motions of some simple sorts of stuff, which would then form the primary division of bodies in the centre of the universe. He also suggested that we should assume only a small number of such sorts of stuff or elements. Especially one should not think that there are infinitely many elements: the elements are to be differentiated by their characteristics, but there is only a limited number of elementary characteristics. Then again, one element is not sufficiecnt for explaining the existence of all the various phenomena in the world. Thus, we should choose a limited number of basic elements that would be differentiated by different characteristics.

We have already seen how Aristotle needs at least one sort of earthly stuff that moves towards the centre of the universe. Then again, he also points out that some things appear to move away from the centre, particularly fire that always move upwards. Between these two stuffs, earth moving always downwards and fire moving always upwards, there appears to be a stuff moving upwards, except when fire stops it – the air – and a stuff moving always downwards, except when earth stops it – water.

Aristotle also describes the relation of the four earthly stuffs or elements in terms of what he describes as basic qualities. The elements can be classified, firstly, according to the capacities of action that they have. Some things are hot, that is, they separate mixed combinations into their constituents and generally activate natural processes inherent in other things. This quality of ”hotness” appears to be associated with the upward movement: air and especially fire are hot. The opposite quality of ”coolness” – the capacity for combining various consituents and generally of hindering natural processes – is then linked to the downward movement of earth and water.

Aristotle also notes a second way to classify elements according to their capacities of receiving effects from other things. The extreme elements or fire and especially earth are dry in the sense that they have a definite shape, but are not easily malleable, while the mediating elements of air and water are moist in the sense that they have no definite shape, but are easily malleable.

Other qualities of elements and of their combinations should then be definable in terms of the four basic qualities. Thus, in a solid object the quality of dryness preponderates and similarly in a liquid object the quality of moistness preponderates.

It is the four primary qualities that actually define the basic elements, and what are usually called earth, water, air and fire are in fact only states of these elements. Particularly the hot and dry element is not always flaming, but could exist as a sort of dry gas, although it is the one most easily flammable: the meteors and comets Aristotle interprets as such inflammations of the hot and dry element.

Aristotle noted that the four earthly elements he had described do appear to change into one another: e.g. when water is applied to fire, a piece of earth is left behind, and when water is heated by fire, vapour or air is generated. In addition to such transformation, the elements can combine and so form more complex entities. The change of earthly things is thus accepted by Aristotle, but what originally instigated such changes? Aristotle's answer is that the earthly changes must eventually be caused by the movement of the heavens and particularly the closest spheres carrying the Sun and the Moon around the Earth.

By themselves, the four elements would in time move into their corresponding layers and remain stable for eternity. The movement of the spheres mixes the different layers, which thus form more like a continuum of different combinations of elements. For instance, atmosphere is formed of both dry and hot or ”fiery” element and moist and hot or ”aerious” element. When the dry air preponderates, the weather is windy, but when the moist air preponderates, clouds are formed and it begins to rain. Sometimes dry gas gets trapped in a cloud, and when it is released, it creates a loud noise called thunder and perhaps bursts into a flame called lightning. Similarly, earthquakes and volcanoes are explained by the dry gas being trapped within the Earth's crust.

The combination of the four basic elements produces then various natural substances. Aristotle never managed to give a detailed classification of all such combinations, but his examples suggest that the analysis of particular substances would have been based on the qualities of the substances in question. Thus, compounds of earth and water with earth in a predominating magnitude are dry and so become solid when heated, while compounds with water in predominating magnitude become solid when frozen. Neither of these things happens to olive oil, so Aristotle concludes that it is actually a combination of air and water.

The combination of elements leads first to substances that do not appear to consist of smaller parts, when the elements mix completely with one another. From such substances then more complex material structures are formed. The most intriguing composed things are undoubtedly living things, and indeed, Aristotle and his followers did spend much time in observing the compositions and behaviours of various plants and animals, thus beginning the sciences of botany and zoology. Aristotle even suggested some preliminary classifications of living things, for instance, he suggested that living things formed a hierarchy from less to more perfect. Yet, he offerred no complete classification and he was definitely against any a priori division of living things: one could not e.g. start in the Platonian manner from a notion of living being and by a constant division into two parts reach all the individual species.

Yet, even after observation and classification of living beings, it still remains uncertain what being alive actually means: what makes certain complex entities e.g. move about on their own accord? Aristotle did not believe that such liveliness would be caused by a separate element – material or immaterial – that could be used to fill bodies, like soup fills a bowl. Liveliness is not also, says Aristotle, identifiable with a single, harmonious state where elements would be mingled with one another in a certain proportion. In fact, the body would, according to this theory, stop being alive at once whenever a human being would fail to find this harmony.

Liveliness is then to be found in a process of living that structurises the passive materials into a living being. What is important in a living being is then the structure that the individual process of living tries to actualise. The materials used might be important in a secondary sense, namely, if the process of life requires certain type of material: for instance, if a living being creates a hard shell around its innards, it can use only hard enough substances for this purpose.

A living being, like a plant, has then a capacity to do certain things, such as nourishing itself when in contact with suitable material. The nourishment enters the living being through its superior part, which in the highest creature or man points towards the most superior parts of the world, and after the living being has appropriated the material it requires, it drops out the unrequired residue. Aristotle emphasises that it is the process of life that is active in the act of nourishment, while the nourishing material is just a means for rejuvenating the passive materials constituting the living entity.

Aristotle also connects the structure of life with his theory of material elements and basic physical qualities. Because heat means the capacity to activate natural processes, living beings as active must be warm rather than cold. But similarly living beings must be moist, because dry objects do not easily change their state, whereas living beings must do this. Thus, a living being must remain warm and moist, and a living entity which fails to retain its natural moistness and which secretes lot of liquid will probably not live very long.

The source of the heat activating the processes of life can then be regarded as the primary source of life. This source resides in the centre of the living thing, for instance, in the heart of a human being. The heat in animals together with their intestines reshapes the food in a form capable of nourishment (the plants do not require such reshaping, because they receive their nourishment in a form directly enjoyable). The final form of the nourishment in the more perfect animals is blood, which is by itself a cold substance, but as animated, acquires heat and then feeds and activates the whole body.

Although heat is central to living, a living being cannot live on mere heat, because mere heat by itself would finally quench itself, just like fire is finally extinguished when it has burned its fuel up. Thus, a living being must also control its heat and cool it in some manner. This is especially true of blooded animals, because animated blood is quite hot. In many blooded animals this happens through respiration, which uses air to cool the body: the exception are fishes that are cooled by the surrounding water. Another source of cooling in animals, according to Aristotle, is the brain, which is supposedly made of cold elements.

Beyond nourishing themselves, most living things can also produce other living beings and thus mimic the eternal movement of stars. Note that Aristotle thinks that not all living things are capable of reproducing. Some species that mix the characteristics of both plants and animals, like starfishes, are generated spontaneously from lifeless matter: a certain type of hot air is capable of instigating a process of life, e.g. in seas where all sorts of materials required for living are to be found. The results of such spontaneous generation cannot produce any offspring themselves – or at least they produce only imperfect offspring, incapable of any further generation.

Plants, according to Aristotle, generate individually, because of their simplicity. In the higher animals generation requires two individuals. One of them – the male – can develop its blood into a form that is capable of generating new living individual, when suitable material is given. This generating agent is semen, a substance generated out of blood and resembling oil in being a foamy mix of water and the forementioned hot air, but also with the capacity of becoming a living animal with sensations and motions.

The material for the semen is provided by the female, who is inferior, says Aristotle, and cannot produce any semen by herself. Instead, the female has an abundance of blood that can be enlivened by semen: if the blood is not used for producing a new living being, it will leak out in menstruation. Just like semen has the capacity of becoming a living animal, the blood in general has the capacity to become alive. After copulation, the semen activates the life of the blood in the woman and creates the central point or the heart, around which the new animal is generated. If the semen can completely control the material it uses, the resulting animal is a male of its kind, capable of producing new semen, and resembling its father. The loss of control means that the animal generated will fall short of perfection: it might be a woman, it might resemble an individual of earlier generation, or in worse case, it might completely fail to have the structure of its own kind.

Living things are not all of the same type, but form a hierarchy according to their capacities, and thus, different animals are generated in different manners. Very cold – that is, very passive – and very dry – that is, very inflexible – animals can only produce quite imperfect offspring that still require some development outside the generating animals: the offspring might be an egg that still grows before turning into a true animal, like with fishes, or even worse, a mere larva that still requires turning into an egglike cocoon before developing into an animal, like with insects. A more active, but still inflexible animal, like bird, can produce a hard egg, which needs not grow itself before turning into an animal; on the other hand, a more flexible, but still passive animal, like shark, can produce a soft and fragile egg, which the animal can turn in its own body into an animal. Finally, both active and flexible animals, like human beings, can produce full animals on their own.

In addition to methods of generation, Aristotle suggests various ways to classify living beings. For instance, plants live through earth, while higher animal life is based on air. Living beings that share characteristics of both animals and plants live in water, which is the element situated between air and earth. Aristotle also hints that Moon might be a home to life based on the fourth element, fire.

A more important differentiating factor is the capacity of sensation. While plants can only regenarate themselves and their species, animals have also the capacity to receive affections from their environment. That is, not to be affected by material things – plants are also affected in this sense – but merely by their outward structure. For instance, through vision an animal is affected in one way by visible or coloured things, in another way by an absence of visibility or darkness and in a third way by an overabundance of visibility or brightness. Usually the senses of the animals are situated at one side called front, which is also the direction to which the animals generally move.

Aristotle thinks that all sense affections require some mediating element, for instance, visible things are mediated by light and sounds and smells by air. Touch and taste Aristotle thinks to be peculiar in that the mediating element is actually a part of the body, that is, flesh and tongue. They are also the most primary forms of sensation, because all animals must be able to feel tangible things and to taste what they are eating. The flesh and the tongue both require some protection: some animals have a hard shell encasing the soft flesh, while others have hard bones keeping the flesh together, and the tongue is hidden behind lips and teeth.

Vision, hearing and smell, on the other hand, are required only by animals capable of movement, which need to sense things from far away. Smell is of these the closest to the contact senses, and indeed, smell and taste are closely connected. Just like tastes have a role in eating, smells vigorate, but only suitably developed animals. Colours, finally, are according to Aristotle the truest form of sensation there is: while e.g. speech of a person may be distorted by the air, the sensed colours should be at least close to how the object itself is coloured. Thus, when two colours form a new colour, the objects having these colours have also been combined into one object.

While some of the affections occur only in one sense, some, such as movement, are common to many senses. Thus, in addition to colours, sight can be used for sensing that a thing moves. In addition to such common sensibles, we may sense in a more figurative way more complex things, just like we can see an anger in a person, when we interpret him to be angry because of certain expressions we literally sense. Aristotle also thinks that the general capacity of sensation reveals not just characteristics of other objects, but also characteristics of ourselves. Thus, through vision we sense not just colour of apples and plumes, but also the fact that we are currently sensing apples and plumes. Aristotle also suggest that the central capacity of sensation lies at the same place as the source of the animal life, namely, at its heart.

When the general capacity to sense is temporarily nullified – e.g. through a certain phase in digestion, Aristotle suggests – the animal enters a state of sleep. Although the sensing proper has stopped, there might still be afterimages or dreams left from the daily events. An animal might even have a better view of his own bodily condition and dream about its possible ailments, because in a dream state the normally minimal signs of sickness are amplified.

In addition to sense, some animals have a capacity for, as it were, perceiving images of things that are not there. This capacity might be a cause of delusions, but it also allows the animals to consider possible outcomes of different processes. Furthermore, this capacity makes the animal capable of remembering previous events. Developed animals could even consciously regulate what they happen to remember through different mnemonic devices.

This capacity of imagining is closely connected with the ability of an animal to move itself for the sake of something. Indeed, without the capacity to remember and ponder possibilities, the animal could not do anything purposefully. This ability to move itself or act is still not completely independent, because it is instigated by something beyond the animal, namely, the desired conclusion of the action. The animal senses or imagines that something is the case and then instantly notes how to obtain what it wants. All this should happen at the centre or the heart of the animal, and from there the impulse to change the state of the body begins. Particularly the impulse to move goes from heart to the joints that move the limbs with the aid of immovable earth. Just as nourishment differentiates between the superior and the inferior parts and sensation between the front and the back, the movement supposedly differentiates between the right and the left: animals begin the movement with their right side.

The highest capacity of a living being is reserved, according to Aristotle, to the highest form of living being, that is, humans: Aristotle even hints that this capacity is transplanted into a generated human being from a source external to the parents. Humans have the capacity to consider not just sensed characteristics, but all sorts of structures in their thinking. Thinking person is then just like a universal capacity for considering all possible things there is to consider. This capacity also gives humans more powers in their deliberation over what to do: they can reason what is truly worth a deed. Beyond this passive capacity, Aristotle suggests, there exists an activity that arouses different structures for the passive capacity to think. This activity, Aristotle thinks, is not anymore capable of change, but exists in a higher realm than mere physical world of variability.